Misplaced Pages

Pfaffian

Article snapshot taken from Wikipedia with creative commons attribution-sharealike license. Give it a read and then ask your questions in the chat. We can research this topic together.

In mathematics , the determinant of an m -by- m skew-symmetric matrix can always be written as the square of a polynomial in the matrix entries, a polynomial with integer coefficients that only depends on m . When m is odd , the polynomial is zero, and when m is even , it is a nonzero polynomial of degree m /2, and is unique up to multiplication by ±1. The convention on skew-symmetric tridiagonal matrices, given below in the examples, then determines one specific polynomial, called the Pfaffian polynomial. The value of this polynomial, when applied to the entries of a skew-symmetric matrix, is called the Pfaffian of that matrix. The term Pfaffian was introduced by Cayley  ( 1852 ), who indirectly named them after Johann Friedrich Pfaff .

#516483

88-431: Explicitly, for a skew-symmetric matrix A {\displaystyle A} , which was first proved by Cayley  ( 1849 ), who cites Jacobi for introducing these polynomials in work on Pfaffian systems of differential equations . Cayley obtains this relation by specialising a more general result on matrices that deviate from skew symmetry only in the first row and the first column. The determinant of such

176-427: A n 0 ] {\displaystyle \Sigma ={\begin{bmatrix}0&a_{1}&0&0\\-a_{1}&0&0&0\\0&0&0&a_{2}\\0&0&-a_{2}&0&\ddots \\&&&\ddots &\ddots &\\&&&&&0&a_{n}\\&&&&&-a_{n}&0\end{bmatrix}}} for real numbers a k {\displaystyle a_{k}} . Now apply

264-646: A and b such that a b {\displaystyle a^{b}} is a rational number . This proof uses that 2 {\displaystyle {\sqrt {2}}} is irrational (an easy proof is known since Euclid ), but not that 2 2 {\displaystyle {\sqrt {2}}^{\sqrt {2}}} is irrational (this is true, but the proof is not elementary). The expression "statistical proof" may be used technically or colloquially in areas of pure mathematics , such as involving cryptography , chaotic series , and probabilistic number theory or analytic number theory . It

352-409: A continuous probability distribution that is peaked around zero and has a parameter that controls for variance can serve as an approximation, in the limit as the variance approaches zero. For example, all three of the above approximations are cumulative distribution functions of common probability distributions: the logistic , Cauchy and normal distributions, respectively. Approximations to

440-447: A mathematical object with a certain property exists—without explaining how such an object can be found. Often, this takes the form of a proof by contradiction in which the nonexistence of the object is proved to be impossible. In contrast, a constructive proof establishes that a particular object exists by providing a method of finding it. The following famous example of a nonconstructive proof shows that there exist two irrational numbers

528-417: A particle physics experiment or observational study in physical cosmology . "Statistical proof" may also refer to raw data or a convincing diagram involving data, such as scatter plots , when the data or diagram is adequately convincing without further analysis. Proofs using inductive logic , while considered mathematical in nature, seek to establish propositions with a degree of certainty, which acts in

616-424: A smooth approximation to the step function, one can use the logistic function H ( x ) ≈ 1 2 + 1 2 tanh ⁡ k x = 1 1 + e − 2 k x , {\displaystyle H(x)\approx {\tfrac {1}{2}}+{\tfrac {1}{2}}\tanh kx={\frac {1}{1+e^{-2kx}}},} where a larger k corresponds to

704-651: A discrete variable n ), is: H [ n ] = { 0 , n < 0 , 1 , n ≥ 0 , {\displaystyle H[n]={\begin{cases}0,&n<0,\\1,&n\geq 0,\end{cases}}} or using the half-maximum convention: H [ n ] = { 0 , n < 0 , 1 2 , n = 0 , 1 , n > 0 , {\displaystyle H[n]={\begin{cases}0,&n<0,\\{\tfrac {1}{2}},&n=0,\\1,&n>0,\end{cases}}} where n

792-402: A large set of candidates. One assigns a certain probability for each candidate to be chosen, and then proves that there is a non-zero probability that a chosen candidate will have the desired property. This does not specify which candidates have the property, but the probability could not be positive without at least one. A probabilistic proof is not to be confused with an argument that a theorem

880-468: A matrix is the product of the Pfaffians of the two matrices obtained by first setting in the original matrix the upper left entry to zero and then copying, respectively, the negative transpose of the first row to the first column and the negative transpose of the first column to the first row. This is proved by induction by expanding the determinant on minors and employing the recursion formula below. (3

968-495: A non-zero imaginary component. For other (more) efficient algorithms see Wimmer 2012 . Mathematical proof A mathematical proof is a deductive argument for a mathematical statement , showing that the stated assumptions logically guarantee the conclusion. The argument may use other previously established statements, such as theorems ; but every proof can, in principle, be constructed using only certain basic or original assumptions known as axioms , along with

SECTION 10

#1732856140517

1056-626: A proof by humans either, especially if the proof contains natural language and requires deep mathematical insight to uncover the potential hidden assumptions and fallacies involved. A statement that is neither provable nor disprovable from a set of axioms is called undecidable (from those axioms). One example is the parallel postulate , which is neither provable nor refutable from the remaining axioms of Euclidean geometry . Mathematicians have shown there are many statements that are neither provable nor disprovable in Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory with

1144-430: A proof is expressed in natural language and is a rigorous argument intended to convince the audience of the truth of a statement. The standard of rigor is not absolute and has varied throughout history. A proof can be presented differently depending on the intended audience. To gain acceptance, a proof has to meet communal standards of rigor; an argument considered vague or incomplete may be rejected. The concept of proof

1232-541: A semantics for what they considered to be the language of thought , whereby standards of mathematical proof might be applied to empirical science . Philosopher-mathematicians such as Spinoza have attempted to formulate philosophical arguments in an axiomatic manner, whereby mathematical proof standards could be applied to argumentation in general philosophy. Other mathematician-philosophers have tried to use standards of mathematical proof and reason, without empiricism, to arrive at statements outside of mathematics, but having

1320-450: A series of lines in two columns. In each line, the left-hand column contains a proposition, while the right-hand column contains a brief explanation of how the corresponding proposition in the left-hand column is either an axiom, a hypothesis, or can be logically derived from previous propositions. The left-hand column is typically headed "Statements" and the right-hand column is typically headed "Reasons". The expression "mathematical proof"

1408-579: A sharper transition at x = 0 . If we take H (0) = ⁠ 1 / 2 ⁠ , equality holds in the limit: H ( x ) = lim k → ∞ 1 2 ( 1 + tanh ⁡ k x ) = lim k → ∞ 1 1 + e − 2 k x . {\displaystyle H(x)=\lim _{k\to \infty }{\tfrac {1}{2}}(1+\tanh kx)=\lim _{k\to \infty }{\frac {1}{1+e^{-2kx}}}.} There are many other smooth, analytic approximations to

1496-699: A signal that switches on at a specified time and stays switched on indefinitely. Heaviside developed the operational calculus as a tool in the analysis of telegraphic communications and represented the function as 1 . Taking the convention that H (0) = 1 , the Heaviside function may be defined as: For the alternative convention that H (0) = ⁠ 1 / 2 ⁠ , it may be expressed as: Other definitions which are undefined at H (0) include: H ( x ) = x + | x | 2 x {\displaystyle H(x)={\frac {x+|x|}{2x}}} The Dirac delta function

1584-504: A similar manner to probability , and may be less than full certainty . Inductive logic should not be confused with mathematical induction . Bayesian analysis uses Bayes' theorem to update a person's assessment of likelihoods of hypotheses when new evidence or information is acquired. Psychologism views mathematical proofs as psychological or mental objects. Mathematician philosophers, such as Leibniz , Frege , and Carnap have variously criticized this view and attempted to develop

1672-561: A single statement: However, this algorithm is unstable when the Pfaffian is large. The eigenvalues of ( σ y ⊗ I n ) T ⋅ A {\displaystyle (\sigma _{y}\otimes I_{n})^{\mathrm {T} }\cdot A} will generally be complex, and the logarithm of these complex eigenvalues are generally taken to be in [ − π , π ] {\displaystyle [-\pi ,\pi ]} . Under

1760-464: A supposed mathematical fact but only do so by neglecting tiny errors (for example, supposedly straight lines which actually bend slightly) which are unnoticeable until the entire picture is closely examined, with lengths and angles precisely measured or calculated. An elementary proof is a proof which only uses basic techniques. More specifically, the term is used in number theory to refer to proofs that make no use of complex analysis . For some time it

1848-518: A value at zero, since such objects are only defined almost everywhere . If using some analytic approximation (as in the examples above ) then often whatever happens to be the relevant limit at zero is used. There exist various reasons for choosing a particular value. Also, H(x) + H(-x) = 1 for all x. An alternative form of the unit step, defined instead as a function H : Z → R {\displaystyle H:\mathbb {Z} \rightarrow \mathbb {R} } (that is, taking in

SECTION 20

#1732856140517

1936-504: Is invertible , one has This can be seen from Aitken block-diagonalization formula, This decomposition involves a congruence transformations that allow to use the Pfaffian property pf ⁡ ( B A B T ) = det ⁡ ( B ) pf ⁡ ( A ) {\displaystyle \operatorname {pf} (BAB^{\mathrm {T} })=\operatorname {det} (B)\operatorname {pf} (A)} . Similarly, when N {\displaystyle N}

2024-428: Is orthogonal and Σ = [ 0 a 1 0 0 − a 1 0 0 0 0 0 0 a 2 0 0 − a 2 0 ⋱ ⋱ ⋱ 0 a n −

2112-680: Is 'probably' true, a 'plausibility argument'. The work toward the Collatz conjecture shows how far plausibility is from genuine proof, as does the disproof of the Mertens conjecture . While most mathematicians do not think that probabilistic evidence for the properties of a given object counts as a genuine mathematical proof, a few mathematicians and philosophers have argued that at least some types of probabilistic evidence (such as Rabin's probabilistic algorithm for testing primality ) are as good as genuine mathematical proofs. A combinatorial proof establishes

2200-406: Is an integer . If n is an integer, then n < 0 must imply that n ≤ −1 , while n > 0 must imply that the function attains unity at n = 1 . Therefore the "step function" exhibits ramp-like behavior over the domain of [−1, 1] , and cannot authentically be a step function, using the half-maximum convention. Unlike the continuous case, the definition of H [0]

2288-459: Is an irrational number : To paraphrase: if one could write 2 {\displaystyle {\sqrt {2}}} as a fraction , this fraction could never be written in lowest terms, since 2 could always be factored from numerator and denominator. Proof by construction, or proof by example, is the construction of a concrete example with a property to show that something having that property exists. Joseph Liouville , for instance, proved

2376-634: Is based on the trace identity and on the observation that pf ( σ y ⊗ I n ) = ( − i ) n 2 {\displaystyle {\textrm {pf}}(\sigma _{y}\otimes I_{n})=(-i)^{n^{2}}} . Since calculating the logarithm of a matrix is a computationally demanding task, one can instead compute all eigenvalues of ( ( σ y ⊗ I n ) T ⋅ A ) {\displaystyle ((\sigma _{y}\otimes I_{n})^{\mathrm {T} }\cdot A)} , take

2464-421: Is believed to be true is known as a conjecture , or a hypothesis if frequently used as an assumption for further mathematical work. Proofs employ logic expressed in mathematical symbols, along with natural language which usually admits some ambiguity. In most mathematical literature, proofs are written in terms of rigorous informal logic . Purely formal proofs , written fully in symbolic language without

2552-450: Is even, then x {\displaystyle x} is even: In proof by contradiction, also known by the Latin phrase reductio ad absurdum (by reduction to the absurd), it is shown that if some statement is assumed true, a logical contradiction occurs, hence the statement must be false. A famous example involves the proof that 2 {\displaystyle {\sqrt {2}}}

2640-446: Is formalized in the field of mathematical logic . A formal proof is written in a formal language instead of natural language. A formal proof is a sequence of formulas in a formal language, starting with an assumption, and with each subsequent formula a logical consequence of the preceding ones. This definition makes the concept of proof amenable to study. Indeed, the field of proof theory studies formal proofs and their properties,

2728-414: Is invertible, one has as can be seen by employing the decomposition Suppose A is a 2n × 2n skew-symmetric matrices, then where σ y {\displaystyle \sigma _{y}} is the second Pauli matrix , I n {\displaystyle I_{n}} is an identity matrix of dimension n and we took the trace over a matrix logarithm . This equality

Pfaffian - Misplaced Pages Continue

2816-473: Is less commonly used to refer to a mathematical proof in the branch of mathematics known as mathematical statistics . See also the " Statistical proof using data " section below. Until the twentieth century it was assumed that any proof could, in principle, be checked by a competent mathematician to confirm its validity. However, computers are now used both to prove theorems and to carry out calculations that are too long for any human or team of humans to check;

2904-577: Is likely that the idea of demonstrating a conclusion first arose in connection with geometry , which originated in practical problems of land measurement. The development of mathematical proof is primarily the product of ancient Greek mathematics , and one of its greatest achievements. Thales (624–546 BCE) and Hippocrates of Chios (c. 470–410 BCE) gave some of the first known proofs of theorems in geometry. Eudoxus (408–355 BCE) and Theaetetus (417–369 BCE) formulated theorems but did not prove them. Aristotle (384–322 BCE) said definitions should describe

2992-427: Is odd, so the Pfaffian of B is 0) The Pfaffian of a 2 n × 2 n skew-symmetric tridiagonal matrix is given as (Note that any skew-symmetric matrix can be reduced to this form; see Spectral theory of a skew-symmetric matrix .) Let A = ( a ij ) be a 2 n × 2 n skew-symmetric matrix. The Pfaffian of A is explicitly defined by the formula where S 2 n is the symmetric group of degree 2 n and sgn(σ)

3080-399: Is often required to compute the Pfaffian of a skew-symmetric matrix S {\displaystyle S} with the block structure where M {\displaystyle M} and N {\displaystyle N} are skew-symmetric matrices and Q {\displaystyle Q} is a general rectangular matrix. When M {\displaystyle M}

3168-407: Is proved that establishes that any arbitrary case implies the next case. Since in principle the induction rule can be applied repeatedly (starting from the proved base case), it follows that all (usually infinitely many) cases are provable. This avoids having to prove each case individually. A variant of mathematical induction is proof by infinite descent , which can be used, for example, to prove

3256-726: Is significant. The discrete-time unit impulse is the first difference of the discrete-time step δ [ n ] = H [ n ] − H [ n − 1 ] . {\displaystyle \delta [n]=H[n]-H[n-1].} This function is the cumulative summation of the Kronecker delta : H [ n ] = ∑ k = − ∞ n δ [ k ] {\displaystyle H[n]=\sum _{k=-\infty }^{n}\delta [k]} where δ [ k ] = δ k , 0 {\displaystyle \delta [k]=\delta _{k,0}}

3344-427: Is the discrete unit impulse function . The ramp function is an antiderivative of the Heaviside step function: ∫ − ∞ x H ( ξ ) d ξ = x H ( x ) = max { 0 , x } . {\displaystyle \int _{-\infty }^{x}H(\xi )\,d\xi =xH(x)=\max\{0,x\}\,.} The distributional derivative of

3432-487: Is the distribution that takes a test function φ to the Cauchy principal value of ∫ − ∞ ∞ φ ( s ) s d s {\displaystyle \textstyle \int _{-\infty }^{\infty }{\frac {\varphi (s)}{s}}\,ds} . The limit appearing in the integral is also taken in the sense of (tempered) distributions. The Laplace transform of

3520-532: Is the signature of σ. One can make use of the skew-symmetry of A to avoid summing over all possible permutations . Let Π be the set of all partitions of {1, 2, ..., 2 n } into pairs without regard to order. There are (2 n )!/(2 n !) = (2 n − 1) !! such partitions. An element α ∈ Π can be written as with i k < j k and i 1 < i 2 < ⋯ < i n {\displaystyle i_{1}<i_{2}<\cdots <i_{n}} . Let be

3608-753: Is the weak derivative of the Heaviside function: δ ( x ) = d d x H ( x ) . {\displaystyle \delta (x)={\frac {d}{dx}}H(x).} Hence the Heaviside function can be considered to be the integral of the Dirac delta function. This is sometimes written as H ( x ) := ∫ − ∞ x δ ( s ) d s {\displaystyle H(x):=\int _{-\infty }^{x}\delta (s)\,ds} although this expansion may not hold (or even make sense) for x = 0 , depending on which formalism one uses to give meaning to integrals involving δ . In this context,

Pfaffian - Misplaced Pages Continue

3696-461: Is used by lay people to refer to using mathematical methods or arguing with mathematical objects , such as numbers, to demonstrate something about everyday life, or when data used in an argument is numerical. It is sometimes also used to mean a "statistical proof" (below), especially when used to argue from data. "Statistical proof" from data refers to the application of statistics, data analysis , or Bayesian analysis to infer propositions regarding

3784-627: The Elements , was read by anyone who was considered educated in the West until the middle of the 20th century. In addition to theorems of geometry, such as the Pythagorean theorem , the Elements also covers number theory , including a proof that the square root of two is irrational and a proof that there are infinitely many prime numbers . Further advances also took place in medieval Islamic mathematics . In

3872-412: The binomial theorem and properties of Pascal's triangle . Modern proof theory treats proofs as inductively defined data structures , not requiring an assumption that axioms are "true" in any sense. This allows parallel mathematical theories as formal models of a given intuitive concept, based on alternate sets of axioms, for example Axiomatic set theory and Non-Euclidean geometry . As practiced,

3960-470: The certainty of propositions deduced in a mathematical proof, such as Descartes ' cogito argument. Sometimes, the abbreviation "Q.E.D." is written to indicate the end of a proof. This abbreviation stands for "quod erat demonstrandum" , which is Latin for "that which was to be demonstrated" . A more common alternative is to use a square or a rectangle, such as □ or ∎, known as a " tombstone " or "halmos" after its eponym Paul Halmos . Often, "which

4048-438: The irrationality of the square root of two . A common application of proof by mathematical induction is to prove that a property known to hold for one number holds for all natural numbers : Let N = {1, 2, 3, 4, ... } be the set of natural numbers, and let P ( n ) be a mathematical statement involving the natural number n belonging to N such that For example, we can prove by induction that all positive integers of

4136-430: The probability of data. While using mathematical proof to establish theorems in statistics, it is usually not a mathematical proof in that the assumptions from which probability statements are derived require empirical evidence from outside mathematics to verify. In physics, in addition to statistical methods, "statistical proof" can refer to the specialized mathematical methods of physics applied to analyze data in

4224-521: The 10th century CE, the Iraqi mathematician Al-Hashimi worked with numbers as such, called "lines" but not necessarily considered as measurements of geometric objects, to prove algebraic propositions concerning multiplication, division, etc., including the existence of irrational numbers . An inductive proof for arithmetic sequences was introduced in the Al-Fakhri (1000) by Al-Karaji , who used it to prove

4312-549: The Heaviside function is the cumulative distribution function of a random variable which is almost surely 0. (See Constant random variable .) Approximations to the Heaviside step function are of use in biochemistry and neuroscience , where logistic approximations of step functions (such as the Hill and the Michaelis–Menten equations ) may be used to approximate binary cellular switches in response to chemical signals. For

4400-863: The Heaviside step function could be made through Smooth transition function like 1 ≤ m → ∞ {\displaystyle 1\leq m\to \infty } : f ( x ) = { 1 2 ( 1 + tanh ⁡ ( m 2 x 1 − x 2 ) ) , | x | < 1 1 , x ≥ 1 0 , x ≤ − 1 {\displaystyle {\begin{aligned}f(x)&={\begin{cases}{\displaystyle {\frac {1}{2}}\left(1+\tanh \left(m{\frac {2x}{1-x^{2}}}\right)\right)},&|x|<1\\\\1,&x\geq 1\\0,&x\leq -1\end{cases}}\end{aligned}}} Often an integral representation of

4488-729: The Heaviside step function is a meromorphic function . Using the unilateral Laplace transform we have: H ^ ( s ) = lim N → ∞ ∫ 0 N e − s x H ( x ) d x = lim N → ∞ ∫ 0 N e − s x d x = 1 s {\displaystyle {\begin{aligned}{\hat {H}}(s)&=\lim _{N\to \infty }\int _{0}^{N}e^{-sx}H(x)\,dx\\&=\lim _{N\to \infty }\int _{0}^{N}e^{-sx}\,dx\\&={\frac {1}{s}}\end{aligned}}} When

SECTION 50

#1732856140517

4576-1121: The Heaviside step function is the Dirac delta function : d H ( x ) d x = δ ( x ) . {\displaystyle {\frac {dH(x)}{dx}}=\delta (x)\,.} The Fourier transform of the Heaviside step function is a distribution. Using one choice of constants for the definition of the Fourier transform we have H ^ ( s ) = lim N → ∞ ∫ − N N e − 2 π i x s H ( x ) d x = 1 2 ( δ ( s ) − i π p . v . ⁡ 1 s ) . {\displaystyle {\hat {H}}(s)=\lim _{N\to \infty }\int _{-N}^{N}e^{-2\pi ixs}H(x)\,dx={\frac {1}{2}}\left(\delta (s)-{\frac {i}{\pi }}\operatorname {p.v.} {\frac {1}{s}}\right).} Here p.v. ⁠ 1 / s ⁠

4664-1029: The Heaviside step function is useful: H ( x ) = lim ε → 0 + − 1 2 π i ∫ − ∞ ∞ 1 τ + i ε e − i x τ d τ = lim ε → 0 + 1 2 π i ∫ − ∞ ∞ 1 τ − i ε e i x τ d τ . {\displaystyle {\begin{aligned}H(x)&=\lim _{\varepsilon \to 0^{+}}-{\frac {1}{2\pi i}}\int _{-\infty }^{\infty }{\frac {1}{\tau +i\varepsilon }}e^{-ix\tau }d\tau \\&=\lim _{\varepsilon \to 0^{+}}{\frac {1}{2\pi i}}\int _{-\infty }^{\infty }{\frac {1}{\tau -i\varepsilon }}e^{ix\tau }d\tau .\end{aligned}}} where

4752-578: The Pfaffian of the 0 × 0 matrix is equal to one. The Pfaffian of a skew-symmetric 2 n × 2 n matrix A with n > 0 can be computed recursively as where the index i can be selected arbitrarily, θ ( i − j ) {\displaystyle \theta (i-j)} is the Heaviside step function , and A ı ^ ȷ ^ {\displaystyle A_{{\hat {\imath }}{\hat {\jmath }}}} denotes

4840-600: The Pfaffian to odd-dimensional matrices is given in the work of de Bruijn on multiple integrals involving determinants. In particular for any m  ×  m matrix A , we use the formal definition above but set n = ⌊ m / 2 ⌋ {\displaystyle n=\lfloor m/2\rfloor } . For m odd, one can then show that this is equal to the usual Pfaffian of an ( m +1) × ( m +1)-dimensional skew symmetric matrix where we have added an ( m +1)th column consisting of m elements 1, an ( m +1)th row consisting of m elements −1, and

4928-450: The accepted rules of inference . Proofs are examples of exhaustive deductive reasoning which establish logical certainty, to be distinguished from empirical arguments or non-exhaustive inductive reasoning which establish "reasonable expectation". Presenting many cases in which the statement holds is not enough for a proof, which must demonstrate that the statement is true in all possible cases. A proposition that has not been proved but

5016-475: The axiom of choice (ZFC), the standard system of set theory in mathematics (assuming that ZFC is consistent); see List of statements undecidable in ZFC . Gödel's (first) incompleteness theorem shows that many axiom systems of mathematical interest will have undecidable statements. While early mathematicians such as Eudoxus of Cnidus did not use proofs, from Euclid to the foundational mathematics developments of

5104-447: The concept being defined in terms of other concepts already known. Mathematical proof was revolutionized by Euclid (300 BCE), who introduced the axiomatic method still in use today. It starts with undefined terms and axioms , propositions concerning the undefined terms which are assumed to be self-evidently true (from Greek "axios", something worthy). From this basis, the method proves theorems using deductive logic . Euclid's book,

5192-2602: The corner element is zero. The usual properties of Pfaffians, for example the relation to the determinant, then apply to this extended matrix. Pfaffians have the following properties, which are similar to those of determinants. Using these properties, Pfaffians can be computed quickly, akin to the computation of determinants. For a 2 n × 2 n skew-symmetric matrix A For an arbitrary 2 n × 2 n matrix B , Substituting in this equation B = A , one gets for all integer m As previously said, A → ∑ i j A i j e i ∧ e j → ∧ n 2 n n ! P f ( A ) e 1 ∧ ⋯ ∧ e 2 n . {\displaystyle A\rightarrow \sum _{ij}A_{ij}e_{i}\wedge e_{j}{\xrightarrow[{}]{\wedge n}}{2^{n}n!}Pf(A)e_{1}\wedge \cdots \wedge e_{2n}.} The same with B A B T {\displaystyle BAB^{\mathrm {T} }} : B A B T → ∑ i j k l B i k B j l A k l e i ∧ e j = ∑ k l A k l f k ∧ f l → ∧ n 2 n n ! P f ( A ) f 1 ∧ ⋯ ∧ f 2 n = 2 n n ! P f ( B A B T ) e 1 ∧ ⋯ ∧ e 2 n , {\displaystyle {\begin{aligned}&BAB^{\mathrm {T} }\rightarrow \sum _{ijkl}B_{ik}B_{jl}A_{kl}e_{i}\wedge e_{j}=\sum _{kl}A_{kl}f_{k}\wedge f_{l}\\&\xrightarrow {\wedge n} {2^{n}n!}Pf(A)f_{1}\wedge \cdots \wedge f_{2n}={2^{n}n!}Pf(BAB^{\mathrm {T} })e_{1}\wedge \cdots \wedge e_{2n},\end{aligned}}} where we defined f k = ∑ i B i k e i {\displaystyle f_{k}=\sum _{i}B_{ik}e_{i}} . Since f 1 ∧ ⋯ ∧ f 2 n = det ( B ) e 1 ∧ ⋯ ∧ e 2 n , {\displaystyle f_{1}\wedge \cdots \wedge f_{2n}=\det(B)e_{1}\wedge \cdots \wedge e_{2n},}

5280-639: The corresponding permutation. Given a partition α as above, define The Pfaffian of A is then given by The Pfaffian of a n × n skew-symmetric matrix for n odd is defined to be zero, as the determinant of an odd skew-symmetric matrix is zero, since for a skew-symmetric matrix, det A = det A T = det ( − A ) = ( − 1 ) n det A , {\displaystyle \det A=\det A^{\text{T}}=\det(-A)=(-1)^{n}\det A,} and for n odd, this implies det A = 0 {\displaystyle \det A=0} . By convention,

5368-930: The equation here ω denotes the wedge product of n copies of ω . Equivalently, we can consider the bivector (which is more convenient when we do not want to impose the summation constraint i < j {\displaystyle i<j} ): ω ′ = 2 ω = ∑ i , j a i j e i ∧ e j , {\displaystyle \omega '=2\omega =\sum _{i,j}a_{ij}\;e_{i}\wedge e_{j},} which gives ω ′ n = 2 n n ! pf ⁡ ( A ) e 1 ∧ e 2 ∧ ⋯ ∧ e 2 n . {\displaystyle \omega '^{n}=2^{n}n!\operatorname {pf} (A)\;e_{1}\wedge e_{2}\wedge \cdots \wedge e_{2n}.} A non-zero generalisation of

SECTION 60

#1732856140517

5456-411: The equivalence of different expressions by showing that they count the same object in different ways. Often a bijection between two sets is used to show that the expressions for their two sizes are equal. Alternatively, a double counting argument provides two different expressions for the size of a single set, again showing that the two expressions are equal. A nonconstructive proof establishes that

5544-402: The existence of transcendental numbers by constructing an explicit example . It can also be used to construct a counterexample to disprove a proposition that all elements have a certain property. In proof by exhaustion, the conclusion is established by dividing it into a finite number of cases and proving each one separately. The number of cases sometimes can become very large. For example,

5632-467: The field of automated proof assistants , this is rarely done in practice. A classic question in philosophy asks whether mathematical proofs are analytic or synthetic . Kant , who introduced the analytic–synthetic distinction , believed mathematical proofs are synthetic, whereas Quine argued in his 1951 " Two Dogmas of Empiricism " that such a distinction is untenable. Proofs may be admired for their mathematical beauty . The mathematician Paul Erdős

5720-569: The first proof of the four color theorem is an example of a computer-assisted proof. Some mathematicians are concerned that the possibility of an error in a computer program or a run-time error in its calculations calls the validity of such computer-assisted proofs into question. In practice, the chances of an error invalidating a computer-assisted proof can be reduced by incorporating redundancy and self-checks into calculations, and by developing multiple independent approaches and programs. Errors can never be completely ruled out in case of verification of

5808-529: The first proof of the four color theorem was a proof by exhaustion with 1,936 cases. This proof was controversial because the majority of the cases were checked by a computer program, not by hand. A closed chain inference shows that a collection of statements are pairwise equivalent. In order to prove that the statements φ 1 , … , φ n {\displaystyle \varphi _{1},\ldots ,\varphi _{n}} are each pairwise equivalent, proofs are given for

5896-550: The form 2 n  − 1 are odd . Let P ( n ) represent " 2 n  − 1 is odd": The shorter phrase "proof by induction" is often used instead of "proof by mathematical induction". Proof by contraposition infers the statement "if p then q " by establishing the logically equivalent contrapositive statement : "if not q then not p ". For example, contraposition can be used to establish that, given an integer x {\displaystyle x} , if x 2 {\displaystyle x^{2}}

5984-474: The gradient of a Pfaffian is given by and the Hessian of a Pfaffian is given by The product of the Pfaffians of skew-symmetric matrices A and B can be represented in the form of an exponential Suppose A and B are 2 n × 2 n skew-symmetric matrices, then and B n ( s 1 , s 2 ,..., s n ) are Bell polynomials . For a block-diagonal matrix For an arbitrary n × n matrix M : It

6072-699: The implications φ 1 ⇒ φ 2 {\displaystyle \varphi _{1}\Rightarrow \varphi _{2}} , φ 2 ⇒ φ 3 {\displaystyle \varphi _{2}\Rightarrow \varphi _{3}} , … {\displaystyle \dots } , φ n − 1 ⇒ φ n {\displaystyle \varphi _{n-1}\Rightarrow \varphi _{n}} and φ n ⇒ φ 1 {\displaystyle \varphi _{n}\Rightarrow \varphi _{1}} . The pairwise equivalence of

6160-400: The involvement of natural language, are considered in proof theory . The distinction between formal and informal proofs has led to much examination of current and historical mathematical practice , quasi-empiricism in mathematics , and so-called folk mathematics , oral traditions in the mainstream mathematical community or in other cultures. The philosophy of mathematics is concerned with

6248-445: The late 19th and 20th centuries, proofs were an essential part of mathematics. With the increase in computing power in the 1960s, significant work began to be done investigating mathematical objects beyond the proof-theorem framework, in experimental mathematics . Early pioneers of these methods intended the work ultimately to be resolved into a classical proof-theorem framework, e.g. the early development of fractal geometry , which

6336-523: The log of all of these and sum them up. This procedure merely exploits the property tr ⁡ log ⁡ ( A B ) = tr ⁡ log ⁡ ( A ) + tr ⁡ log ⁡ ( B ) {\displaystyle \operatorname {tr} {\log {(AB)}}=\operatorname {tr} {\log {(A)}}+\operatorname {tr} {\log {(B)}}} . This can be implemented in Mathematica with

6424-409: The matrix A with both the i -th and j -th rows and columns removed. Note how for the special choice i = 1 {\displaystyle i=1} this reduces to the simpler expression: One can associate to any skew-symmetric 2 n × 2 n matrix A = ( a ij ) a bivector where { e 1 , e 2 , ..., e 2 n } is the standard basis of R . The Pfaffian is then defined by

6512-419: The most famous and surprising being that almost all axiomatic systems can generate certain undecidable statements not provable within the system. The definition of a formal proof is intended to capture the concept of proofs as written in the practice of mathematics. The soundness of this definition amounts to the belief that a published proof can, in principle, be converted into a formal proof. However, outside

6600-479: The previous theorem, we have p f ( A ) 2 = p f ( Σ ) 2 det ( Q ) 2 = p f ( Σ ) 2 = ( ∏ a i ) 2 = det ( A ) {\displaystyle pf(A)^{2}=pf(\Sigma )^{2}\det(Q)^{2}=pf(\Sigma )^{2}=\left(\prod a_{i}\right)^{2}=\det(A)} . If A depends on some variable x i , then

6688-539: The proof is finished. Since pf ⁡ ( A ) 2 = det ( A ) {\displaystyle \operatorname {pf} (A)^{2}=\det(A)} is an equation of polynomials, it suffices to prove it for real matrices, and it would automatically apply for complex matrices as well. By the spectral theory of skew-symmetric real matrices , A = Q Σ Q T {\displaystyle A=Q\Sigma Q^{\mathrm {T} }} , where Q {\displaystyle Q}

6776-601: The role of language and logic in proofs, and mathematics as a language . The word "proof" comes from the Latin probare (to test). Related modern words are English "probe", "probation", and "probability", Spanish probar (to smell or taste, or sometimes touch or test), Italian provare (to try), and German probieren (to try). The legal term "probity" means authority or credibility, the power of testimony to prove facts when given by persons of reputation or status. Plausibility arguments using heuristic devices such as pictures and analogies preceded strict mathematical proof. It

6864-450: The second representation is easy to deduce from the first, given that the step function is real and thus is its own complex conjugate. Since H is usually used in integration, and the value of a function at a single point does not affect its integral, it rarely matters what particular value is chosen of H (0) . Indeed when H is considered as a distribution or an element of L (see L space ) it does not even make sense to talk of

6952-432: The sense of distributions . In general, however, pointwise convergence need not imply distributional convergence, and vice versa distributional convergence need not imply pointwise convergence. (However, if all members of a pointwise convergent sequence of functions are uniformly bounded by some "nice" function, then convergence holds in the sense of distributions too .) In general, any cumulative distribution function of

7040-400: The statements then results from the transitivity of the material conditional . A probabilistic proof is one in which an example is shown to exist, with certainty, by using methods of probability theory . Probabilistic proof, like proof by construction, is one of many ways to prove existence theorems . In the probabilistic method, one seeks an object having a given property, starting with

7128-728: The step function. Among the possibilities are: H ( x ) = lim k → ∞ ( 1 2 + 1 π arctan ⁡ k x ) H ( x ) = lim k → ∞ ( 1 2 + 1 2 erf ⁡ k x ) {\displaystyle {\begin{aligned}H(x)&=\lim _{k\to \infty }\left({\tfrac {1}{2}}+{\tfrac {1}{\pi }}\arctan kx\right)\\H(x)&=\lim _{k\to \infty }\left({\tfrac {1}{2}}+{\tfrac {1}{2}}\operatorname {erf} kx\right)\end{aligned}}} These limits hold pointwise and in

7216-403: The sum of two even integers is always even: This proof uses the definition of even integers, the integer properties of closure under addition and multiplication, and the distributive property . Despite its name, mathematical induction is a method of deduction , not a form of inductive reasoning . In proof by mathematical induction, a single "base case" is proved, and an "induction rule"

7304-404: The summation, for a real valued Pfaffian, the argument of the exponential will be given in the form x + k π / 2 {\displaystyle x+k\pi /2} for some integer k {\displaystyle k} . When x {\displaystyle x} is very large, rounding errors in computing the resulting sign from the complex phase can lead to

7392-425: The value of which is zero for negative arguments and one for positive arguments. Different conventions concerning the value H (0) are in use. It is an example of the general class of step functions, all of which can be represented as linear combinations of translations of this one. The function was originally developed in operational calculus for the solution of differential equations , where it represents

7480-486: Was known for describing proofs which he found to be particularly elegant as coming from "The Book", a hypothetical tome containing the most beautiful method(s) of proving each theorem. The book Proofs from THE BOOK , published in 2003, is devoted to presenting 32 proofs its editors find particularly pleasing. In direct proof, the conclusion is established by logically combining the axioms, definitions, and earlier theorems. For example, direct proof can be used to prove that

7568-456: Was thought that certain theorems, like the prime number theorem , could only be proved using "higher" mathematics. However, over time, many of these results have been reproved using only elementary techniques. A particular way of organising a proof using two parallel columns is often used as a mathematical exercise in elementary geometry classes in the United States. The proof is written as

7656-408: Was to be shown" is verbally stated when writing "QED", "□", or "∎" during an oral presentation. Unicode explicitly provides the "end of proof" character, U+220E (∎) (220E(hex) = 8718(dec)) . Heaviside step function The Heaviside step function , or the unit step function , usually denoted by H or θ (but sometimes u , 1 or 𝟙 ), is a step function named after Oliver Heaviside ,

7744-409: Was ultimately so resolved. Although not a formal proof, a visual demonstration of a mathematical theorem is sometimes called a " proof without words ". The left-hand picture below is an example of a historic visual proof of the Pythagorean theorem in the case of the (3,4,5) triangle . Some illusory visual proofs, such as the missing square puzzle , can be constructed in a way which appear to prove

#516483